Free Novel Read

What Is Life (Canto Classics)




  WHAT IS LIFE?

  with

  MIND AND MATTER

  &

  AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL

  SKETCHES

  WHAT IS LIFE?

  The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell

  with

  MIND AND MATTER

  &

  AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL

  SKETCHES

  ERWIN SCHRÖDINGER

  CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS

  Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo,

  Delhi, Mexico City

  Cambridge University Press

  The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK

  Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York

  www.cambridge.org

  Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107604667

  What is Life? and Mind and Matter

  © Cambridge University Press 1967

  WHAT IS LIFE?

  First published 1944

  Reprinted 1945, 1948, 1951, 1955, 1962

  MIND AND MATTER

  First published 1958

  Reprinted 1959

  Combined reprint 1967

  Canto edition with Autobiographical Sketches and

  Foreword to What is Life? by Roger Penrose

  © Cambridge University Press 1992

  First printed 1992

  14th printing 2013

  Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CRO 4YY

  ISBN 978-1-107-60466-7 Paperback

  Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy

  of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this

  publication, and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is,

  or will remain, accurate or appropriate.

  Contents

  WHAT IS LIFE?

  Preface

  1 THE CLASSICAL PHYSICIST’S APPROACH TO THE SUBJECT

  The general character and the purpose of the investigation

  Statistical physics. The fundamental difference in structure

  The naïve physicist’s approach to the subject

  Why are the atoms so small?

  The working of an organism requires exact physical laws

  Physical laws rest on atomic statistics and are therefore only approximate

  Their precision is based on the large number of atoms intervening. 1st example (paramagnetism)

  2nd example (Brownian movement, diffusion)

  3rd example (limits of accuracy of measuring)

  The √ n rule

  2 THE HEREDITARY MECHANISM

  The classical physicist’s expectation, far from being trivial, is wrong

  The hereditary code-script (chromosomes)

  Growth of the body by cell division (mitosis)

  In mitosis every chromosome is duplicated

  Reductive division (meiosis) and fertilization (syngamy)

  Haploid individuals

  The outstanding relevance of the reductive division

  Crossing-over. Location of properties

  Maximum size of a gene

  Small numbers

  Permanence

  3 MUTATIONS

  ‘Jump-like’ mutations – the working-ground of natural selection

  They breed true, i.e. they are perfectly inherited

  Localization. Recessivity and Dominance

  Introducing some technical language

  The harmful effect of close-breeding

  General and historical remarks

  The necessity of mutation being a rare event

  Mutations induced by X-rays

  First law. Mutation is a single event

  Second law. Localization of the event

  4 THE QUANTUM-MECHANICAL EVIDENCE

  Permanence unexplainable by classical physics

  Explicable by quantum theory

  Quantum theory – discrete states-quantum jumps

  Molecules

  Their stability dependent on temperature

  Mathematical interlude

  First amendment

  Second amendment

  5 DELBRÜCK’S MODEL DISCUSSED AND TESTED

  The general picture of the hereditary substance

  The uniqueness of the picture

  Some traditional misconceptions

  Different ‘states’ of matter

  The distinction that really matters

  The aperiodic solid

  The variety of contents compressed in the miniature code

  Comparison with facts: degree of stability; discontinuity of mutations

  Stability of naturally selected genes

  The sometimes lower stability of mutants

  Temperature influences unstable genes less than stable ones

  How X-rays produce mutation

  Their efficiency does not depend on spontaneous mutability

  Reversible mutations

  6 ORDER, DISORDER AND ENTROPY

  A remarkable general conclusion from the model

  Order based on order

  Living matter evades the decay to equilibrium

  It feeds on ‘negative entropy’

  What is entropy? – The statistical meaning of entropy

  Organization maintained by extracting ‘order’ from the environment

  7 IS LIFE BASED ON THE LAWS OF PHYSICS?

  New laws to be expected in the organism

  Reviewing the biological situation

  Summarizing the physical situation

  The striking contrast

  Two ways of producing orderliness

  The new principle is not alien to physics

  The motion of a clock

  Clockwork after all statistical

  Nernst’s Theorem

  The pendulum clock is virtually at zero temperature

  The relation between clockwork and organism

  EPILOGUE. ON DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL

  MIND AND MATTER

  1 THE PHYSICAL BASIS OF CONSCIOUSNESS

  The problem

  A tentative answer

  Ethics

  2 THE FUTURE OF UNDERSTANDING

  A biological blind alley?

  The apparent gloom of Darwinism

  Behaviour influences selection

  Feigned Lamarckism

  Genetic fixation of habits and skills

  Dangers to intellectual evolution

  3 THE PRINCIPLE OF OBJECTIVATION

  4 THE ARITHMETICAL PARADOX: THE ONENESS OF MIND

  5 SCIENCE AND RELIGION

  6 THE MYSTERY OF THE SENSUAL QUALITIES

  AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL SKETCHES

  Translated by Schrödinger’s granddaughter Verena

  WHAT IS LIFE?

  THE PHYSICAL ASPECT OF THE LIVING CELL

  Based on lectures delivered under the auspices of the Dublin Institute for

  Advanced Studies at Trinity College, Dublin, in February 1943

  To

  the memory of

  My Parents

  Foreword

  When I was a young mathematics student in the early 1950s I did not read a great deal, but what I did read – at least if I completed the book – was usually by Erwin Schrödinger. I always found his writing to be compelling, and there was an excitement of discovery, with the prospect of gaining some genuinely new understanding about this mysterious world in which we live. None of his writings possesses more of this quality than his short classic What is Life? – which, as I now realize, must surely rank among the most influential of scientific writings in this century. It represents a powerful attempt to comprehend some of the genuine mysteries of life, mad
e by a physicist whose own deep insights had done so much to change the way in which we understand what the world is made of. The book’s cross-disciplinary sweep was unusual for its time – yet it is written with an endearing, if perhaps disarming, modesty, at a level that makes it accessible to non-specialists and to the young who might aspire to be scientists. Indeed, many scientists who have made fundamental contributions in biology, such as J. B. S. Haldane and Francis Crick, have admitted to being strongly influenced by (although not always in complete agreement with) the broad-ranging ideas put forward here by this highly original and profoundly thoughtful physicist.

  Like so many works that have had a great impact on human thinking, it makes points that, once they are grasped, have a ring of almost self-evident truth; yet they are still blindly ignored by a disconcertingly large proportion of people who should know better. How often do we still hear that quantum effects can have little relevance in the study of biology, or even that we eat food in order to gain energy? This serves to emphasize the continuing relevance that Schrödinger’s What is Life? has for us today. It is amply worth rereading!

  Roger Penrose

  8 August 1991

  Preface

  A scientist is supposed to have a complete and thorough knowledge, at first hand, of some subjects and, therefore, is usually expected not to write on any topic of which he is not a master. This is regarded as a matter of noblesse oblige. For the present purpose I beg to renounce the noblesse, if any, and to be freed of the ensuing obligation. My excuse is as follows:

  We have inherited from our forefathers the keen longing for unified, all-embracing knowledge. The very name given to the highest institutions of learning reminds us, that from antiquity and throughout many centuries the universal aspect has been the only one to be given full credit. But the spread, both in width and depth, of the multifarious branches of knowledge during the last hundred odd years has confronted us with a queer dilemma. We feel clearly that we are only now beginning to acquire reliable material for welding together the sum total of all that is known into a whole; but, on the other hand, it has become next to impossible for a single mind fully to command more than a small specialized portion of it.

  I can see no other escape from this dilemma (lest our true aim be lost for ever) than that some of us should venture to embark on a synthesis of facts and theories, albeit with second-hand and incomplete knowledge of some of them – and at the risk of making fools of ourselves.

  So much for my apology.

  The difficulties of language are not negligible. One’s native speech is a closely fitting garment, and one never feels quite at ease when it is not immediately available and has to be replaced by another. My thanks are due to Dr Inkster (Trinity College, Dublin), to Dr Padraig Browne (St Patrick’s College, Maynooth) and, last but not least, to Mr S. C. Roberts. They were put to great trouble to fit the new garment on me and to even greater trouble by my occasional reluctance to give up some ‘original’ fashion of my own. Should some of it have survived the mitigating tendency of my friends, it is to be put at my door, not at theirs.

  The head-lines of the numerous sections were originally intended to be marginal summaries, and the text of every chapter should be read in continuo.

  E.S.

  Dublin

  September 1944

  Homo liber nulla de re minus quam de morte cogitat; et ejus sapientia non mortis sed vitae meditatio est. SPINOZA’S Ethics, Pt IV, Prop. 67

  (There is nothing over which a free man ponders less than death; his wisdom is, to meditate not on death but on life.)

  CHAPTER 1

  The Classical Physicist’s

  Approach to the Subject

  Cogito ergo sum.

  DESCARTES

  THE GENERAL CHARACTER AND THE PURPOSE OF

  THE INVESTIGATION

  This little book arose from a course of public lectures, delivered by a theoretical physicist to an audience of about four hundred which did not substantially dwindle, though warned at the outset that the subject-matter was a difficult one and that the lectures could not be termed popular, even though the physicist’s most dreaded weapon, mathematical deduction, would hardly be utilized. The reason for this was not that the subject was simple enough to be explained without mathematics, but rather that it was much too involved to be fully accessible to mathematics. Another feature which at least induced a semblance of popularity was the lecturer’s intention to make clear the fundamental idea, which hovers between biology and physics, to both the physicist and the biologist.

  For actually, in spite of the variety of topics involved, the whole enterprise is intended to convey one idea only – one small comment on a large and important question. In order not to lose our way, it may be useful to outline the plan very briefly in advance.

  The large and important and very much discussed question is:

  How can the events in space and time which take place within the spatial boundary of a living organism be accounted for by physics and chemistry?

  The preliminary answer which this little book will endeavour to expound and establish can be summarized as follows:

  The obvious inability of present-day physics and chemistry to account for such events is no reason at all for doubting that they can be accounted for by those sciences.

  STATISTICAL PHYSICS. THE FUNDAMENTAL

  DIFFERENCE IN STRUCTURE

  That would be a very trivial remark if it were meant only to stimulate the hope of achieving in the future what has not been achieved in the past. But the meaning is very much more positive, viz. that the inability, up to the present moment, is amply accounted for.

  Today, thanks to the ingenious work of biologists, mainly of geneticists, during the last thirty or forty years, enough is known about the actual material structure of organisms and about their functioning to state that, and to tell precisely why, present-day physics and chemistry could not possibly account for what happens in space and time within a living organism.

  The arrangements of the atoms in the most vital parts of an organism and the interplay of these arrangements differ in a fundamental way from all those arrangements of atoms which physicists and chemists have hitherto made the object of their experimental and theoretical research. Yet the difference which I have just termed fundamental is of such a kind that it might easily appear slight to anyone except a physicist who is thoroughly imbued with the knowledge that the laws of physics and chemistry are statistical throughout.1 For it is in relation to the statistical point of view that the structure of the vital parts of living organisms differs so entirely from that of any piece of matter that we physicists and chemists have ever handled physically in our laboratories or mentally at our writing desks.2 It is well-nigh unthinkable that the laws and regularities thus discovered should happen to apply immediately to the behaviour of systems which do not exhibit the structure on which those laws and regularities are based.

  The non-physicist cannot be expected even to grasp – let alone to appreciate the relevance of – the difference in ‘statistical structure’ stated in terms so abstract as I have just used. To give the statement life and colour, let me anticipate what will be explained in much more detail later, namely, that the most essential part of a living cell – the chromosome fibre – may suitably be called an aperiodic crystal. In physics we have dealt hitherto only with periodic crystals. To a humble physicist’s mind, these are very interesting and complicated objects; they constitute one of the most fascinating and complex material structures by which inanimate nature puzzles his wits. Yet, compared with the aperiodic crystal, they are rather plain and dull. The difference in structure is of the same kind as that between an ordinary wallpaper in which the same pattern is repeated again and again in regular periodicity and a masterpiece of embroidery, say a Raphael tapestry, which shows no dull repetition, but an elaborate, coherent, meaningful design traced by the great master.

  In calling the periodic crystal one of the most complex objects of
his research, I had in mind the physicist proper. Organic chemistry, indeed, in investigating more and more complicated molecules, has come very much nearer to that ‘aperiodic crystal’ which, in my opinion, is the material carrier of life. And therefore it is small wonder that the organic chemist has already made large and important contributions to the problem of life, whereas the physicist has made next to none.

  THE NAÏVE PHYSICIST’S APPROACH

  TO THE SUBJECT

  After having thus indicated very briefly the general idea – or rather the ultimate scope – of our investigation, let me describe the line of attack.

  I propose to develop first what you might call ‘a naïve physicist’s ideas about organisms’, that is, the ideas which might arise in the mind of a physicist who, after having learnt his physics and, more especially, the statistical foundation of his science, begins to think about organisms and about the way they behave and function and who comes to ask himself conscientiously whether he, from what he has learnt, from the point of view of his comparatively simple and clear and humble science, can make any relevant contributions to the question.

  It will turn out that he can. The next step must be to compare his theoretical anticipations with the biological facts. It will then turn out that – though on the whole his ideas seem quite sensible – they need to be appreciably amended. In this way we shall gradually approach the correct view – or, to put it more modestly, the one that I propose as the correct one.

  Even if I should be right in this, I do not know whether my way of approach is really the best and simplest. But, in short, it was mine. The ‘naïve physicist’ was myself. And I could not find any better or clearer way towards the goal than my own crooked one.

  WHY ARE THE ATOMS SO SMALL?

  A good method of developing ‘the naïve physicist’s ideas’ is to start from the odd, almost ludicrous, question: Why are atoms so small? To begin with, they are very small indeed. Every little piece of matter handled in everyday life contains an enormous number of them. Many examples have been devised to bring this fact home to an audience, none of them more impressive than the one used by Lord Kelvin: Suppose that you could mark the molecules in a glass of water; then pour the contents of the glass into the ocean and stir the latter thoroughly so as to distribute the marked molecules uniformly throughout the seven seas; if then you took a glass of water anywhere out of the ocean, you would find in it about a hundred of your marked molecules.3